John Austin (legal philosopher)

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Jump to navigation
Jump to search

For the 20th-century linguistic philosopher, see J. L. Austin .
John Austin
John Austin.jpg
Born(1790-03-03)3 March 1790
Creeting Mill, Suffolk
Died1 December 1859(1859-12-01) (aged 69)
Weybridge, Surrey
Era 19th-century philosophy
Region Western philosophy
School Legal positivism
Main interests
Legal philosophy
Notable ideas
Criticism of natural law
Influences
  • Jeremy Bentham
Influenced
  • Joseph Raz , H. L. A. Hart

John Austin (3 March 1790 – 1 December 1859) was a noted English legal theorist who strongly influenced British and American law with his analytical approach to jurisprudence and his theory of legal positivism . In opposing traditional ” natural law ” approaches, Austin argued against any necessary connections between law and morality. Human legal systems, he claimed, can and should be studied in an empirical, value-free way.

Contents

  • 1 Life and work
  • 2 Legal positivism
  • 3 Criticism
  • 4 References
  • 5 Further reading
  • 6 External links

Life and work[ edit ]

Austin was born on 3 March 1790 at Creeting St Mary , the eldest son of a well-to-do Suffolk miller.

After spending five years in the army during the Napoleonic Wars, Austin turned to law and spent seven unhappy years practising at the Chancery bar. In 1819, Austin married Sarah Taylor and became neighbours and close friends with Jeremy Bentham and James and John Stuart Mill . Mainly through Bentham’s influence, Austin was appointed professor of jurisprudence at the newly founded University of London in 1826. Austin’s lectures were not well-attended, and he resigned his university post in 1834.

Thereafter, aside from two stints on government commissions, Austin lived largely on his wife’s earnings as a writer and translator. Plagued by ill health, depression and self-doubt, Austin wrote little after the publication of his major work, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (1832). This work was largely ignored during Austin’s lifetime. It became influential only after his death when his wife, Sarah Austin , published a second edition in 1861. A second book, Lectures on Jurisprudence, was put together by Sarah from Austin’s notes and published in 1863. [1]

John Austin died on 1 December 1859 in Weybridge . His only daughter, Lucie , later became Lady Duff-Gordon.

Legal positivism[ edit ]

Austin’s goal was to transform law into a true science. To do this, he believed it was necessary to purge human law of all moralistic notions and to define key legal concepts in strictly empirical terms. Law, according to Austin, is a social fact and reflects relations of power and obedience. This twofold view, that (1) law and morality are separate and (2) that all human-made (“positive”) laws can be traced back to human lawmakers, is known as legal positivism. Drawing heavily on the thought of Jeremy Bentham, Austin was the first legal thinker to work out a full-blown positivistic theory of law.

Austin argues that laws are rules, which he defines as a type of command. More precisely, laws are general commands issued by a sovereign to members of an independent political society, and backed up by credible threats of punishment or other adverse consequences (“sanctions”) in the event of non-compliance. The sovereign in any legal system is that person, or group of persons, habitually obeyed by the bulk of the population, which does not habitually obey anyone else. A command is a declared wish that something should be done, issued by a superior, and accompanied by threats in the event of non-compliance. Such commands give rise to legal duties to obey. Note that all the key concepts in this account (law, sovereign, command, sanction, duty) are defined in terms of empirically verifiable social facts. No moral judgment, according to Austin, is ever necessary to determine what the law is — though of course morality must be consulted in determining what the law should be. As a utilitarian, Austin believed that laws should promote the greatest happiness of society.

Criticism[ edit ]

Though Austin’s brand of legal positivism was greatly influential in the late 19th and early 20th centuries, [2] it is widely seen as overly simplistic today. [3] Critics such as H. L. A. Hart have charged that Austin’s account fails to recognize that:
(1) In many modern societies, lawmaking power is dispersed and it is very difficult to identify a “sovereign” in Austin’s sense.
(2) Most legal systems include rules that don’t impose sanctions, but empower officials or citizens to do certain things (e.g., to make wills), or specify ways that legal rules may be identified or changed.
(3) Those threats do not give rise to obligations. If they did, there would be no essential difference between a gunman’s threat (“Your money or your life”) and an ordinary piece of legislation. [4]

References[ edit ]

  1. ^ Hart, H. L. A., “Introduction,” in John Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, H. L. A. Hart (ed.), New York: The Noonday Press, 1954, pp. vii-ix.
  2. ^ Morison, W. L., John Austin. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1982, pp. 148–77.
  3. ^ Altman, Andrew, Arguing about Law: An Introduction to Legal Philosophy, 2nd ed., Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 2001, pp. 69–70.
  4. ^ Hart, H. L. A., “Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morality.” Harvard Law Review, 71: 593–629 (1958).

Further reading[ edit ]

  • Hart, H. L. A. (2012). The Concept of Law, 3rd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 
  • Morison, W. L. (1982). John Austin. Stanford: Stanford University Press. 
  • Rumble, Wilfred E. (1985). The Thought of John Austin: Jurisprudence, Colonial Reform, and the British Constitution. London: Athlone Press. 

External links[ edit ]

  • Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). “John Austin” . Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . 
  • Wikisource logo Works written by or about John Austin at Wikisource
  • Quotations related to John Austin (legal philosopher) at Wikiquote
  • Spencer about Austin’s system https://web.archive.org/web/20140202205618/http://www.constitution.org/hs/manvssta.txt a short way into essay #4
  • v
  • t
  • e
Jurisprudence
Legal theory
  • Critical legal studies
  • Comparative law
  • Economic analysis
  • International legal theory
  • Legal history
  • Philosophy of law
  • Sociology of law
Philosophers
  • Alexy
  • Allan
  • Aquinas
  • Aristotle
  • Austin
  • Beccaria
  • Bentham
  • Betti
  • Bickel
  • Blackstone
  • Bobbio
  • Bork
  • Brożek
  • Cardozo
  • Castanheira Neves
  • Chafee
  • Coleman
  • Del Vecchio
  • Durkheim
  • Dworkin
  • Ehrlich
  • Feinberg
  • Fineman
  • Finnis
  • Frank
  • Fuller
  • Gardner
  • George
  • Green
  • Grisez
  • Grotius
  • Gurvitch
  • Habermas
  • Han
  • Hart
  • Hegel
  • Hobbes
  • Hohfeld
  • Hägerström
  • Jellinek
  • Jhering
  • Kant
  • Kelsen
  • Köchler
  • Kramer
  • Llewellyn
  • Lombardía
  • Luhmann
  • Lundstedt
  • Lyons
  • MacCormick
  • Marx
  • Nussbaum
  • Olivecrona
  • Pashukanis
  • Perelman
  • Petrazycki
  • Pontes de Miranda
  • Posner
  • Pound
  • Puchta
  • Pufendorf
  • Radbruch
  • Rawls
  • Raz
  • Reale
  • Reinach
  • Renner
  • Ross
  • Rumi
  • Savigny
  • Scaevola
  • Schmitt
  • Shang
  • Simmonds
  • Somló
  • Suárez
  • Tribe
  • Unger
  • Voegelin
  • Waldron
  • Walzer
  • Weber
Theories
  • Analytical jurisprudence
  • Deontological ethics
  • Interpretivism
  • Legalism
  • Legal moralism
  • Legal positivism
  • Legal realism
  • Libertarian theories of law
  • Natural law
  • Paternalism
  • Utilitarianism
  • Virtue jurisprudence
Concepts
  • Dharma
  • Fa
  • Judicial interpretation
  • Justice
  • Legal system
  • Li
  • Rational-legal authority
  • Usul al-Fiqh
Related articles
  • Law
  • Political philosophy
  • more…
  • Category Category
  • Portal Law portal
  • Philosophy portal
  • WikiProject WikiProject Law
  • WikiProject Philosophy
  • changes
Authority control Edit this at Wikidata
  • WorldCat Identities
  • BNF : cb122834666 (data)
  • GND : 118505181
  • ISNI : 0000 0001 1025 845X
  • LCCN : n81139369
  • NDL : 00620297
  • NLA : 35010308
  • SNAC : w6tt8011
  • SUDOC : 028020758
  • VIAF : 44360401

Retrieved from ” https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=John_Austin_(legal_philosopher)&oldid=848869479 ”
Categories :

  • 19th-century British philosophers
  • 1790 births
  • 1859 deaths
  • Philosophers of law
  • Academics of University College London
  • British legal scholars
  • Consequentialists
  • Utilitarians
  • English legal writers
  • People from Creeting St Mary
  • Members of the Inner Temple
  • 19th-century English writers
Hidden categories:

  • Articles with hCards
  • Wikipedia articles with BNF identifiers
  • Wikipedia articles with GND identifiers
  • Wikipedia articles with ISNI identifiers
  • Wikipedia articles with LCCN identifiers
  • Wikipedia articles with NDL identifiers
  • Wikipedia articles with NLA identifiers
  • Wikipedia articles with SNAC-ID identifiers
  • Wikipedia articles with SUDOC identifiers
  • Wikipedia articles with VIAF identifiers